*Note to my readers: The following article has been written by a friend that studies philosophy and is also familiar with the Gangadeanian worldview. I think he raises some interesting challenges against some of the things that Anderson as argued in print. It's nice to see a different perspective or angle highlighted. Perhaps I'll add my reaction to this piece in the comments or with a followup post.
Clarity, Skepticism, and Disagreement
I recently found myself looking over Anderson’s book The Clarity of God’s Existence wherein he tries to defend the audacious claim that God’s existence must be maximally clear if, as Historic Christianity teaches, persons are maximally responsible for belief in God. Anderson entertains several attempts to avoid the need for clarity – skepticism, fideism, probability/plausibility, mysticism, etc. – in order to undermine these positions. In my perusal of the book, Anderson’s discussion of skepticism seemed particularly inadequate.
I recently found myself looking over Anderson’s book The Clarity of God’s Existence wherein he tries to defend the audacious claim that God’s existence must be maximally clear if, as Historic Christianity teaches, persons are maximally responsible for belief in God. Anderson entertains several attempts to avoid the need for clarity – skepticism, fideism, probability/plausibility, mysticism, etc. – in order to undermine these positions. In my perusal of the book, Anderson’s discussion of skepticism seemed particularly inadequate.
He
points out that many think that knowledge of God isn’t possible given
widespread and intractable disagreement over the question of whether God
exists. I interpret Anderson’s construal of this particular kind of skepticism
to be this: Given that there is irresolvable disagreement over whether God
exists, this fact is evidence that God can’t be known (i.e., God’s existence is
unclear). Alternatively, Anderson argues that the mere fact that there is
irresolvable disagreement over the question of whether God exists doesn’t show
that God can’t be known; rather, he proposes, it shows that not all seek to know God. I take Anderson to be saying
that irresolvable disagreement over God’s existence is better explained by the possibility that not all seek to know God
rather than the possibility that God’s existence is unclear.
I
have several concerns about Anderson’s critique of skepticism vis-à-vis
clarity. For example, he merely proposes the possibility that not all seek to know God without explaining what
he means by ‘seek.’ This seems to be another manifestation of the Gangadeanian
tendency to confidently assert terms without providing any corresponding
analysis (something the administrator of this blog has routinely criticized: http://reasontodoubt.blogspot.com/2015/06/objectivity-in-art-another-symptom-of.html).
Further, he seems to employ an inference to the best explanation (IBE), but it’s
not clear how an IBE – a form of probabilistic reasoning – comports with
Anderson’s commitment to a strong sense of knowledge in which one can be epistemically certain that God exists
(See http://reasontodoubt.blogspot.com/2015/04/anderson-on-knowledge-vs-knowledge.html).
In addition, Anderson fails to inform the reader how the possibility that not
all seek to know God explains why there is intractable disagreement concerning
God’s existence. Without any elucidation on this mark, the reader is at a loss
as to how to judge the probabilistic strength of Anderson’s IBE in comparison
with competing explanations.
Despite
these concerns, I wish to raise a more serious skeptical problem for Anderson.
He cites the fact of irresolvable disagreement over the question of whether God
exists as a reason why the skeptic thinks that God’s existence is epistemically
unclear. However, note that disagreement considerations with respect to some
question can be divided into two different kinds of worries:
First-order worries:
disagreement over some proposition, P,
directly undermines the evidence for P.
Higher-order worries:
disagreement over some proposition, P,
directly undermines the claim that one has rationally assessed the evidence for
P.
My
reading of Anderson’s discussion of skepticism inclines me to think that he is
primarily preoccupied with first-order worry with respect to disagreement over
God’s existence. Yet, the more pressing challenge for clarity arises from the
higher-order worry, which has been called within the philosophical literature
the epistemological problem of peer disagreement. The problem of peer
disagreement can be put as follows: how ought one to treat the reliability of one’s
cognitive faculties with respect to some question (in our case, the question of
whether God exists) when one finds oneself in a disagreement with a peer (an
individual who is seemingly equally qualified, informed, and intellectually
virtuous)? Philosophers who work on this problem argue over whether one is
issued a higher-order worry when one finds that a peer has reached a conclusion
that contradicts one’s own. That is, philosophers argue over whether one ought
to give one’s disputant equal-weight and conciliate or whether one should
remain steadfast in one’s conclusion despite the fact that one’s peer believes
differently from oneself. Regardless of whether one thinks that one ought to
conciliate or remain steadfast in these situations, it must be granted that the
higher-order challenge that disagreement presents is the more pressing worry
for any commitment to clarity. If it turns out that conciliation is a more
rational response in these situations, then one ought to lower one’s confidence
in the proposition that God exists. And if one ought to lower one’s confidence
in the proposition that God exists, then irresolvable disagreement among peers entails that one can’t be certain
that God exists (i.e. God’s existence is not clear).
With
the more challenging skeptical problem for clarity vis-à-vis peer disagreement
before us, how should one in fact
respond when one finds oneself in these situations? I assume that Anderson will
hold that it is rational to remain steadfast in circumstances of peer
disagreement, and so in the remaining portion of this post, I will try to
persuade Anderson (and his followers) that there is something rationally
untenable about a steadfast response and that a position more akin to
conciliation (i.e. reducing one’s confidence in one’s position) is more
rationally acceptable.
To
get a sense of the problem with a full-blown steadfast position, consider the
following example from David Christensen (‘Disagreement, Question-Begging and
Epistemic Self-Criticism’).
Mental Math: After a nice
restaurant meal, my friend and I decide to tip 20% and split the check,
rounding up to the nearest dollar. As we have done many times, we do the math
in our heads. We have a long and equally good track record at this (in the
cases where we’ve disagreed, checking with a calculator has shown us right
equally frequently); and I have no reason (such as those involving alertness or
tiredness or differential consumption of coffee or wine) for suspecting one of
us to be especially good, or bad, at the current reasoning task. I come up with
$43; but then my friend announces that she got $45.
In
the Mental Math case, many philosophers argue that I should become
significantly less confident that my portion of the bill is $43. This is
because I am not able to adduce any reasons that are independent of my disputed reasoning for thinking that I am right
about my share of the bill. Christensen contends that there would be something
unacceptably question-begging if I were to maintain confidence that my portion
of the bill is $43 by arguing as follows: “Since my friend fails to see that
the facts support an answer of $43, I have good reason for thinking that,
contrary to my expectation, she is not (at least at this moment) a reliable
judge of the question we are disputing; therefore, her disagreement gives me no
reason at all to question my answer.” To argue like this would be circular
since I would be assuming the reliability of my reasoning even though my
reasoning is the very thing the disagreement with my friend is calling into
question. To avoid circularity, I need to provide reasons independent of my
disputed reasoning that show me to be a more superior calculator than my
friend. If I can’t provide any dispute-independent reasons, then, Christensen
holds, I ought to lower confidence in my position.
These
considerations from Christensen ought to show Anderson what would be rationally
unacceptable about preserving his high level of confidence in the question of
whether God exists when engaged in peer disagreement. When Anderson disagrees
with a peer over God’s existence (that
is, when he disagrees with someone who is aware of all of the same arguments,
inferences, and evidence), how ought he to respond? In order to remain
steadfast, Anderson needs to provide a dispute-independent reason to think that
he has more rationally assessed the evidence concerning the question at hand.
However, it’s hard to see what kind of independent reason Anderson could
proffer given that his disputant is in possession of all of the same arguments,
inferences, and evidence. Unless Anderson can provide a dispute-independent
reason, he ought to conciliate by reducing his confidence that God’s existence
is as clear as he thinks.
There
have been many proposed strategies to avoid the conciliatory pressure that
disagreement presents, none of which Anderson will find appealing. In order to
avoid full-blown skepticism, some argue that question-begging responses are
rationally acceptable in cases where a dispute-independent evaluation fails to
give one a reason to think that one’s disputant is equally credentialed (Christensen,
op. cit., 15). Anderson needs to determine, however, whether he is comfortable
with using circular reasoning in order to avoid the skeptical threat. Others
have attempted to deflect skeptical pressure by appealing to externalist
considerations (Plantinga, ‘‘Pluralism: A Defense of Religious Exlusivism’).
Plantinga argues that, although there may be parity among internal epistemic
factors between two disputants (i.e. symmetry among argument, inference, and
evidence), this need not mean that there is parity among external epistemic factors (e.g. properly functioning cognitive
faculties within environment aimed at truth). Yet, I doubt that Anderson will
find this strategy attractive given his commitment to an internalist
conceptualization of knowledge and justification (See http://reasontodoubt.blogspot.com/2014/12/anderson-on-externalism-vs-internalism.html).
Others have tried to avoid skeptical pressure by appealing to more Bayesian
theories of rationality. Pittard articulates a particular way of
probabilistically conditionalizing on disagreement (he calls it
‘instrumentalism’) and argues that, since religious disagreements involve one’s
most fundamental rational starting points, it is not possible to take up a position
antecedent to them in order to employ
Bayes’ theorem. Therefore, any response to disagreement will have to make use
of those fundamental rational starting points, which will result in a readout
that is inevitably self-favoring (Pittard, ‘Fundamental Disagreements and the
Limits of Instrumentalism,’ MSS). However,
Anderson probably won’t find appeals to Bayesian rationality and probabilistic
reasoning helpful (See Clarity, pp.
28-9, where he criticizes probability/plausibility to avoid clarity). And
others have tried to avoid the skeptical pressure of disagreement by appealing
to ‘permissive’ theories of rationality, which says that, in some cases, a body
of evidence can warrant more than one rational conclusion. For example, subject
A can rationally believe p given E and subject B can rationally believe ~p given E, and disagreement between A and B need not require conciliation because both A and B have rationally responded to E (See
Schoenfield, ‘Permission to Believe’).
These
strategies of avoiding global skepticism with respect to disagreement-related
concerns are by no means exhaustive. My intention in citing these various
proposals is only to show that (1) there have been some novel ways of avoiding
full-blown skepticism, and (2) that Anderson has his work cut out for him since
I take it he won’t find any of these proposals compelling. However, lest
clarity be threatened by disagreement, it is incumbent on Anderson to
articulate a theory of how one ought to respond to disagreement that avoids extreme
conciliation. Yet, if it’s true that Anderson is committed to internalism, and
if the problem of disagreement assumes symmetry prevails among disputants with
respect to internal epistemic factors (argument, inference, evidence), I’m not
sure how Anderson can advocate for steadfastness without having to accept the
viability of some kind of benign circularity. I will leave it to Anderson to
decide whether circularity is an appropriate response to disagreement.
What
I hope to have modestly shown is that skepticism is by no means easily
defeated. Anderson unfortunately characterized a weak form of skepticism, but
I’ve tried to demonstrate that a more threatening form is to be found in terms
of the higher-order worry of peer disagreement. Although I don’t think that
disagreement needs to force one to be skeptical of all of one’s beliefs, I
think that we need to consider seriously how widespread disagreement with
equally qualified individuals might negatively bear on the reliability of our
reasoning on various theoretical issues. Such an evaluation of our cognitive
abilities will divulge, I think, that our epistemic lives are far more messier
and fallible than Anderson would have us believe, which might imply that God
isn’t as clear to our reasoning abilities as Anderson unreservedly holds.
If Anderson is doing an "inference to the best explanation" in order to derive the conclusion that (at least some) people do not seek to know what is clear, then you're right that it's tenuous since this sort of inductive reasoning doesn't seem consistent with the kinds of standards that Gangadean requires for knowledge. So maybe Anderson will have to claim that he doesn't actually know that people don't seek (at least unless he has some other means of knowing this). Good point. If, on the other hand, he thinks of the phenomena of disagreement (over what he takes as clear) is a potential defeater to his view that it is clear, and then he is responding in order to explain away the potential defeater by the proposal that at least some people are not "seeking" properly, then the worry is that this isn't motivated properly (i.e., it stinks of ad hoccery). So if he's taking this second route, he will need to motivate this view independently of the fact that it saves his other claims. So either way, he needs an independent argument for the conclusion that it is clear and that disagreements arise due to the failure to seek.
ReplyDeleteI think you're right that a question of what it is that counts as "seeking" in the relevant sense is relevant at this point. Since Gangadean and his people are so intent on presenting air-tight proofs you would expect to be ultra precise on their terms. Especially since they preach that meaning is more basic than truth, if they affirm that people do not seek (in fact, given their Calvinism, they think apart from an act of God, no one seeks) they should know and be able to "show" just what counts as seeking vs. not-seeking.
On the point about peer disagreement and higher-order defeat. I'm not sure what I think yet. I suspect that Anderson would be inclined to say that someone who doesn't agree with the conclusion that God exists (after having read and understood Gangadean's "proofs") is not an epistemic peer because they are not seeking. Your point seems to be that this would be question begging for Anderson and company. Or at least there is no way for Gangadean to make good on his claim--he has to prove that such a person is not seeking rather than merely state it. I think this is right.
Now I wonder if Anderson could turn around and accuse you of begging the question in insisting that they are epistemic peers to begin with. In other words, maybe the issues of peer disagreement and higher order defeat seem to arise only after it is granted that there at least appear to be epistemic peers that disagree with us. So someone that isn't already convinced that there are such thing as epistemic peers in disagreements might not feel the weight of higher order issues.