Sunday, January 11, 2015

Gangadean on the Problem of Evil.

One purported solution to the problem of evil is to give an account of a positive or morally good reason for which God would permit evil.  On the view I have in mind (Gangadeanian/Westminster Fellowship), God "permits" moral evil (e.g., sin) to reveal his divine justice and mercy. Natural evil in turn, is imposed (by God) in order to restrict, remove, and recall man from moral evil. The idea is that suffering in various forms (toil, strife, old age, sickness and death) makes us stop and think (where not thinking/seeking and thus not knowing certain fundamental propositions is the root of our moral evil). I will explore of few criticisms I have against this view.

For one thing, we need to get clearer on what this account of God and his relation to evil amounts to. The view I have in mind takes it that God is not the author of sin, but simply permits man to sin (this is stated in the Westminster confession of faith).  I don't think this distinction helps or even makes much sense. It seems to me a playing around with words to avoid an unfavorable philosophical conclusion. After all we need to ask what then is the cause of moral evil? Gangadeanians will say that humans by their very nature are mutable beings--we necessarily either change towards good or evil. Further, it is God that must uphold us if we are to avoid changing towards evil. This represents a Calvinistic committment that Gangadean maintains. So if we want to explain why there is moral evil, why there was a fall, then it looks like we turn to the fact that humans are created to necessarily change, and apart from God's upholding, necessarily towards evil. But this is hardly an attractive picture.

Think about it.  On this picture (what I take to be Gangadean's view), God creates humans with a particular design in mind and with foreknowledge about what this design entails. He creates man such that man is essentially changeable (among other things). This means man must (necessarily) change for good or for evil.  Further, God creates man in such a way that unless God sustains him, he will necessarily sin (that is, he must change for evil). Again God knows this due to his foreknowledge. Still, as the story goes, God creates man (i.e. a being that must sin if not upheld by God) and then stops upholding him.

The result of course is that man sins --indeed there was no other way it could go. If God created man and all the sufficient conditions for man to sin, then God is the ultimate source of sin.  If this doesn't count as "author" of sin, then I don't know what does. Perhaps the Gangadeanians take "author" to mean something like "the most immediate source". But why does immediacy make a relevant difference here?  Think about the holocaust.  The soldiers carrying out the executions were more immediately connected to particular genocides than Hitler, but that doesn't allow that Hitler was any less responsible for the executions. My intention to bang a hammer against a nail is less immediately connected to the hammer hitting the head of the nail, but surely my intention is an essential cause or source of the nail going into whatever surface it happens penetrating. Examples abound. If there's some other notion of author (as distinct from permitter) that is relevant, then Gangadean needs to explain this. What is important is that God is the creator of all things including the necessary and sufficient conditions for man to sin on Gangadean's picture. And this is all I can think 'author of sin' to mean. My suspicion is that there is a real tension here between Gangadean's soft determinist/compatibilist views and his desire to not implicate God in discussing the ultimate origin of sin.

A further issue arises when we consider what Gangdaean et al. mean by 'sin'/'moral evil.' Gangadean and company believe that evil/sin is defined as acting against one's nature and good is to act according to one's nature. But then what are we to make of a good human in light of the metaphysical views that Gangadean is committed to in fleshing out his theodicy? If the picture is that humans when not upheld by God are such that they must sin, isn't this saying something about the nature of humanity? So then shouldn't we define a "good" human in light of this essential fact about humans? Again God created us a particular way such that without his upholding, we have to sin. But since he stopped sustaining man from sin, it seems that it would be good (according to the above definition) for man to sin when not being upheld by God. So then did man really sin? Alternatively, it would be evil for man to seek consistently apart from God. Things are equally as tricky when we think about what it means that man is born into sin (i.e., the doctrine of total depravity). Was there some metaphysical change in humans after the fall?  If so again, shouldn't we alter our definition of what it means to be human (i.e., the nature of humanity)?  In turn we'd have to redefine what is good for post-fall humans and of course, what is evil.  That is to say, man post-fall is a being that is in total depravity and so good for this being is to be in total depravity to it's fullest.  Now if the fall of man was not a metaphysical change, then in what sense is it impossible for man to seek God without an act of God?  So denying that the fall changed man fundamentally seems to have the problem that we can't account for total depravity.  Now one might have this idea of "ideal man" in mind.  But I need to ask what the basis of this notion comes from?  This "ideal man" must be something like "how God created man to be".  But you see the problem, don't you?  If God created man to be a particular way, then that is just how man would need to be.  So how we are is how God created us to be (unless you allow that humans can stray from God's design/intention). So there appears to be a dilemma with two unattractive horns here for the Gangadeanians.

A third and more focused issue pertaining to the theodicy is that Gangadean assumes (rather than proves) too much to employ it. So let's grant for the sake of discussion that natural evil (non-agent driven evil) is imposed by God as a call back from moral evil. The problem is we'd be dishonest if we didn't wonder whether God could have figured out a different way (in all his knowledge and power) to reveal himself without requiring all this evil. Does the earth have to have so many people?  Do so many people have to grow old and sick and die?  Couldn't we have been compelled by a story of hypotheticals?  It seems to me that God could have simply made us believe how things would go if we were to sin. Say, in a vision or simply by telling us subjunctive conditionals in a compelling way. We could then gain true beliefs about God this way and come to know him. More specifically, but rather crudely we might say that if revelation is the goal of God he could have written a "book version" of human history that was convincing. Adam and Eve could be created in this world and then God tells them, look, supposing that you were to sin, this is all that would happen [enter vision of hypotheticals involving the fall, evil and redemption].  Gangadean in his book actually addresses this in his attempt to offer a theodicy.  He writes,
It [the theodicy] assumes, second, that there is no other way to deepen the revelation of divine justice and mercy. Some things cannot be known except by experience-- such as hunger or pain, both physical and spiritual.  A book version of human history, or a movie version, cannot supply this experience and is incomprehensible without it.  Virtual reality works insofar as it is distinguishable from reality.  Some experience is necessary for imagination to work, so there is no way to deepen the revelation apart from providence in the fall and redemption of mankind.
Yes, Gangadean's theodicy does assume a lot, we agree on that much. But does he support these assumptions?  Not really. As far as I can tell, he just gives us more controversial assumptions. For instance, is it certain that some things can only be known via experience? Hunger? Physical and spiritual pain?  How would we even begin to verify this? Sure it might seem common sensical, but Gangadean surely wouldn't rest his views on common sense. Further, doesn't God know what it is like to be hungry?  In pain?  If not, are there things that God doesn't know?  Further, does virtual reality work only on the basis of its being distinguishable from reality? Again how does he know this to be true?  Why think that "Some experience is necessary for imagination to work?" How does he know so much about what is requisite for imagination from the arm chair? These are mere assertions or intuitions that Gangadean seems to make but each of these points should not be taken for granted.

Gangadean also gets wind of a further problem which is the issue of whether this revelation of God's justice and mercy are worth all the suffering. It's natural to ask whether divine revelation is a worthwhile goal when considering the cost. That is, according to some Christian accounts (including Gangadean's) a lot of people are going to suffer eternally (just try and wrap your mind around unending suffering for lots and lots of people). So is it worth it that God reveals who he is to us if the cost is so grave?  Sadly, the author gives only this in response:
Thirdly, it [the theodicy] assumes that the deepened revelation and knowledge of this revelation is worth the suffering.  This third assumption is not so clear because it can be asked before or after the revelation is seen and it can be asked of those who do see it and of those who never come to see it.  Here testimony is relevant.  Job struggled before seeing, and, after seeing, was silenced in awe and repentance.  Paul the Apostle said the sufferings of this life cannot be compared with the glory that is to be revealed.  Many throughout the ages have confessed the same.  The figure of the pearly gates symbolizes that through suffering we come into the knowledge of the glory of God.  The answer to the question "Is it worth it?" is a presumed unqualified yes. (Emphasis mine). 
On one reading of this text, it seems to me that Gangadean has lost sight of the dialectic here. On this reading, the bible (which is revelation from God) gives us the answer that suffering is worth it (for the believer).  Hence his appeal to the testimony of Job and Paul. So we can trust this testimony insofar as it is part of God's word (and so infallibly true). Now if the problem of evil is set up against Theism, it is inappropriate to appeal to biblical passages qua revelation from God (which presupposes God exists) to inform a premise of an argument used to rescue theism from the problem of evil.  Indeed the way he and Owen Anderson present it in their classes, they take the problem of evil to be devastating to theism if left unaddressed. [ Note: I disagree with this since, the problem of evil is not really a logical problem. It is an evidential problem (i.e., isn't the pervasive nature of evil some evidence against God's existence) as most philosophers of religion see it.] So the point is, you can't then presuppose God exists (and that the bible is the word of God) in order to argue that God exists despite all the evil in the world.

A second reading is something like, "well look there are what these persons in this book say and it feels right to me too."  This would be a very weak argument. (Perhaps this is why he hedges his statement above with "presumed unqualified yes"? Italics mine.) I don't really get what a "presumed unqualified yes" is.  Presumptions are qualifications after all.  In other words, his answer is something like "a qualified, unqualified yes."  And there's good reason to qualify this answer.  I mean, it is far from obvious that all this suffering is worth the revelation that Christians get about God's justice and mercy. Now from the vantage point of one challenging theism on grounds of the problem of evil I would offer this response.  Who cares what these people named Job and Paul are thought to be saying in some purported revelation (I say this because we are trying not to presuppose that the bible is the word of God yet)?  What makes them right? So there are no legs to this reading of the answer to the question of "is it worth it?"

Alternatively, maybe Gangadean just thinks it's intuitive. Christians get a sense that they know God and think it is the best thing since sliced bed.  So they are willing to allow that grave suffering of millions upon millions of persons (some who will suffer eternally!) is worth it.  But I certainly don't share this intuition, even as a believer.  More importantly, just because a bunch of Christians (who are on the winning side) feel good about it, doesn't make it true that it is in fact worth all the suffering.  Worth it to whom?  To those who are eternally dammed?  That's doubtful.  Further, it seems consistent for even a Christian who is not going to be spiritually dead for eternity, that it isn't worth it because they feel compassion for those that don't make the cut.  One might then be tempted to talk about value (i.e., whether it is worth it) from some objective vantage point, but one wonders if this makes much sense.

I think what the person questioning whether all the evil is worth the revelation is getting at is whether it is ultimately consistent with the idea that God is perfectly good.  Here we get to the question I raised above about whether God's creating beings that must necessarily sin apart from him, is consistent with his being all good.








5 comments:

  1. If Gangadean believes God's existence is clear to reason (certain) and that this is true for everyone through general revelation, how could natural evil "deepen" that knowledge? It's already as deep as it could possibly be!

    And second, if experiences and testimony are needed for us to discover this "deepened revelation", doesn't this rely on inductive inferences? (something not certain)?

    ReplyDelete
  2. Thanks for your comments. Let me see if I can try to respond in the way that a Gangadeanian might.

    As to your first worry, I think they would say that the clarity of a proposition doesn't imply that a potential knower actually knows the proposition. Knowing requires the desire to know and a certain process of seeking/reasoning to be instantiated by the seeker, and of course a lot of other facts about the seeker's psychology, going correctly or normally.
    So the idea seems to be that despite the revelation being as clear as can be, there are impediments to this revelation, which can only be removed by way of natural evil/suffering. Of course, this last claim is highly controversial. Why should we think that suffering and to the extent that it exists in our world is required and/or sufficient for removing any such impediments to knowing what is clear? How could Gangadean know that this is so?

    As to your second point, I'm at a loss to say how they might respond. Perhaps their position is simply to deny that anything like inductive reasoning from experiences, and fallible sources of belief formation (e.g., testimony) are involved in learning about the revelation via suffering. Of course, this is also HIGHLY contentious and so I'd be curious to see how they would rational justify this claim. So great point!


    ReplyDelete
    Replies
    1. To the first point, what about Gangadean himself? He claims to have a logical proof, which to him is psychologically and logically certain. So why would he ever experience suffering? Why would God need to "call him back", given that Gangadean has dedicated his life to articulating clarity?

      If "the clarity of a proposition doesn't imply that a potential knower actually knows the proposition" is true, then this would also apply to Gangadean. That is, how does Gangadean KNOW that he knows? If he's an internalist, does he accept the KK principal? It seems that it would apply here, which creates a dilemma for him, and his entire project. If proof is not persuasion, than persuasion is also not proof.

      Delete
    2. I don't think he claims to know all that is clear to reason/knowable. As I understand it, he takes himself to know some of the things that are clear to reason, but he also takes himself to be ignorant about others. Moreover, since he's a kind of extreme internalist, knowledge comes and goes with retrospective awareness of the proofs upon which knowledge rests. Of course, we may forget proofs or not be inclined to recite them/think of them at any given time. Pairing this with his requirement that "one knows that p only if one is able to prove that p" and you get the result that all of us frequently vacillate between knowing and not-knowing for any given proposition.

      So per 1), Gangadean would likely admit that he doesn't know everything that is clear, and this is because he doesn't seek consistently (since seeking is sufficient for knowing what is clear) and 2) Gangadean's epistemological views appear to commit him to the view that knowledge comes and goes quite easily. And I guess this is where natural evil comes in.

      With respect to 2), while I think Gangadean's views on knowledge do lead to the unsavory position that knowledge comes and goes like the weather, I don't know that Gangadean would claim that natural evil serves to call one back from that kind of epistemic vacillation. It would be problematic if he did since the kind of ignorance I have in mind doesn't seem necessarily the result of not seeking. At least in some cases it actually seems like a fact about the kind of beings we are. We don't have perfect memories and we simply can't walk around CONSTANTLY being disposed to reciting proofs of every last thing we know/knew. So it would be weird if we were in some way "called back" from something we can't actually change or overcome.

      I do strongly suspect that Gangadean does maintain 1) and ties this to natural evil. But perhaps a similar problem arises for this view. It seems to me that the question to raise at this point is whether or not Gangadean thinks we, as finite beings, with the kind of psychological hardwiring we have, would in fact be able to know all that is clear (provided we were seeking consistently). And I'm not sure what his position is on that. If the number of things that can be known is too small, then I think your first challenge has some bite. After all, you might think, if it's sufficiently small, Gangadean must certainly know all of them. On the other hand, if the number is too large (such that not even an ideal human that only consistently seeks could know them all), then once again it's just weird that natural evil would "call us back" from something we can't possibly change about ourselves. So I suppose his view must be that the number of clear propositions is such that a subject that only seeks consistently, knows all of them. And there is actually no human that seeks consistently (viz. there exists no sinless person), which is why natural evil is imposed upon all, including Gangadean. I think there are some serious issues with this result that maybe I'll followup with in a future article.

      Delete
    3. As to whether "clarity of p" implies "p is known": on the face of it, there isn't anything too weird about this. Many epistemologists draw the distinction between, "S knowing p" and "S being in a position to know p." The first requires that our subject actually knows a proposition, which entails that she at least believes that proposition. While the latter doesn't require that the proposition be believed. Instead, S can be in a position to know that p, because she has great evidence for p (and is not in a Gettier situation), and so if she WERE to believe p, she would know that p. It seems to me that Gangadean is just drawing a slightly different distinction, in the same spirit. Something like, "knowing p" on the one hand and "p being knowable/clear." Further, the latter is being cashed out in terms of the the following subjunctive conditional: "if S seeks to know what is clear, then she will know it." Seeking, according to Gangadean, is both necessary and sufficient for knowing what is clear. Of course, it isn't clear what analysis he wants to offer for "seeking." And that's no minor point. Much will ride on how he fills in the details for what counts as seeking vs. not-seeking.

      As to whether Gangadean accepts KK or whether his views commit him to that controversial principle, I'm not sure, but I suspect that it does. The way that he and Anderson criticize externalist theories of knowledge inclines me to think that they accept something like it. But I guess I'm not understanding how KK relates to the distinction between "p being clear to reason for S" and "S knowing p." Perhaps I'm misunderstanding you?

      Anyway, thanks for the very interesting comments!


      Delete